The End of Silent Rites
Philip Ball: Elegant
Solutions: Ten Beautiful Experiments in Chemistry, The Royal
Society of Chemistry, Cambridge, UK, 2005, vii+212 pp. [ISBN
0-85404-674-7]
by Joachim Schummer*
In 2002 the American Chemical Society (ACS)
asked
its members to submit proposals for the "ten most beautiful experiments
in chemistry" (C&EN, Nov. 18, 2002, p. 5) and then proudly
published the result of the vote in its Chemical and Engineering
News magazine (C&EN,
Aug. 25, 2003, pp. 27-30). Democratic as the procedure is, it avoids
asking critical questions: What is an experiment? What is beauty? What
is chemistry? In fact, you need not be able to give an answer to these
questions in order to vote. We could even imagine none of the voters
being able to answer any of the questions in explicit terms. And yet,
the members of the society might correctly consider the result valid,
not only with regard to the top ten list but also regarding its
implicit definitions of what ‘experiment’, ‘beauty’, and ‘chemistry’
means. The result thus reflects the tacit knowledge and the
unquestioned feelings of the majority, as they have previously been
trained to respond to such unusual questions, and helps newcomers to
acculturate easily. However, such implicit consensus definitions and
assessments are neither binding for non-members, nor suitable for
explicit debates. Prompted by the questions of what a beautiful
experiment in chemistry is, you might repeat the top ten list you have
learnt by heart, but otherwise remain silent.
Now imagine that ‘beautiful’ is just another
term
for ‘important’ and that ‘experiments’ means whatever chemists are
doing in their labs. How can you educate young chemists to become
researchers doing important chemistry if you avoid discussing what
‘important’ means? They can gather the meaning of ‘importance’ from the
role models of the top ten list, you might respond. The list includes,
of course, the most famous heroes from the history of chemistry and
captures their most important breakthrough experiments. By copying or
transferring to current research issues the heroic deeds of the past,
young scholars can accomplish excellence. Now, if the key to doing
important chemistry is learning from the history of chemistry, why did
the ACS encourage doing history of chemistry in the clumsiest manner
one can imagine – by collecting and ranking decontextualized historical
‘facts’ and anecdotes from the memory of its members who used to have
no training in the history of chemistry? Because the scholarly
historiography of chemistry does not matter here, you might respond.
What matters is only what today’s chemists consider to be important
chemistry of the past, be that invented anecdotes or not. The reference
to the past only serves as a means to communicate about the values of
today – in lack of an explicit discourse about values such as
importance. In other words, the democratic ranking is a rite of the
tribe of the chemists.
Why and how then did such an accomplished
science
writer as Philip Ball create his own list of "ten beautiful experiments
in chemistry"? On the one hand, the project was commissioned by the
British Royal Society of Chemistry, in response to the ACS ranking, of
course. On the other, Ball has in fact been seriously searching for the
role of aesthetics in chemistry before, though not in the design of
experiments. Thus, the book was from the outset a compromise, but one
that helped him counterbalance and, I am sure, redirect the chemists’
interest in beauty. In almost any regard, he puts emphasis on the
opposite of the ACS approach, even if his list of experiments, at first
glance, greatly overlaps with that of the ACS. Thus, the book starts
out with conceptual clarifications. It questions the concept of
experiment as theory testing, which has led generations of philosophers
of science to such absurdities as ‘astronomical experiments’, and
emphasizes the explorative, manipulative, and technological character
of chemical experiments. Unlike the ACS, it rejects the idea that a
beautiful experiment must be significant or important in retrospect and
rules out any serendipity findings of whatever later importance.
Instead of providing a ranking, Ball’s ten experiments are each meant
to illustrate one aspect of beauty. And throughout the section called
‘Asking Questions of Nature’, it elaborates on the difficult historical
distinction between chemistry and physics.
Most important, however, Ball does not
present a
‘list’ of ten experiments, that simple-minded readers could learn by
heart, but ten chapters, each exploring an episode in the history of
chemistry, from van Helmont’s 17th-century experimental approach to the
latest achievements in synthetic chemistry. A remedy against the
isolated historical ‘facts’ collected by the ACS, Ball heavily
contextualizes ‘his experiments’ by providing scientific,
philosophical, social, and biographical background information,
sometimes to the extent that ‘the experiment’ almost vanishes within
the narrative. Moreover, he does away with plenty of anecdotes and myth
that the chemistry community and its hagiographers have uncritically
spun around their history, from the Wöhler myth to the romancing
of
numerous chemical heroes. And what is more, he discusses why chemists
of all scientists have such a particular need for historical myths and
romances (pp. 119-123).
The book is not free of small errors or
misleading interpretations, such when Bacon’s choice of his book title Novum
Organum is said to be a metaphor for applied science (p. 2) rather
than an allusion to Aristotle’s Organon;
when Lavoisier is made the single author of the New System of
Nomenclature (p. 31); or when Pasteur’s rejection of spontaneous
generation is interpreted as an anti-vitalist move (p. 115). All that
is forgivable, however, in the face of the wealth of historical details
and in-depth interpretations that are usually based on the latest
history of science scholarship. What makes this book particular strong
is that it is readily accessible by a general readership with all its
historical intricacy and scientific details included. Indeed, Ball is
even able to explain in simple words the Woodward-Hoffmann rules, which
he needs to make plausible an aesthetic feature of chemical synthesis.
Since each of the ten chapters highlights one
feature of the beauty of chemical experiments, they seem to be
conceived as individually sufficient conditions rather than as
altogether necessary conditions of beauty. This suggests that Ball has
ten different concepts or aspects of beauty in mind, which are, in the
order of the chapters,
- exact quantification (van Helmont),
- attention to details (Cavendish),
- patience in the conduct of the experiment (Marie Curie),
- elegance in the design of the experiment (Ernest
Rutherford),
- miniaturization and acceleration of the experiment (various
nuclear chemistry groups),
- conceptual simplicity (Louis Pasteur),
- imagination that transcends common views (Stanley Miller),
- simple-minded, straightforward reasoning (Neil Bartlett),
- economy, avoidance of deviations (Robert B. Woodward), and
- conceptually straightforward design (Leo Paquette).
Although I have pushed Ball’s own terms a
little
bit, it seems obvious that all the ten features are first of all
virtues of the experimenter (Ball’s main examples are listed above in
brackets) rather than attributes of specific experiments in which these
virtues have been materialized. Two important consequences follow from
that distinction.
First, the shift from specific historical
experiments to experimental virtues allows a more general analysis.
Virtues, i.e.
attitudes and capacities of people, can be more readily transferred
from context to context; here, from the specific historical contexts to
current research issues. (This is why, in ethics, moral virtues have
been preferred over moral values, norms, and consequences by many
philosophers since Aristotle.) Thus, provided Ball’s experimental
virtues are generally accepted, his analysis of beauty provides a much
better educational approach than the rite of the ACS.
Second, ‘beautiful’ is a normative concept
that
belongs to the realm of aesthetics, besides ‘true’ (epistemological),
‘right’ (moral), and ‘important’ for something else (instrumental). As
far as I can see, Ball’s concepts of beauty are clearly distinguished
from epistemological and moral concepts. Moreover, the focus on virtues
allows decontextualizing the experiments and thus abstracts from their
historical (i.e. instrumental) importance, i.e. the
experimental virtues of each of the examples are valuable regardless of
the historical importance of the specific experiments in retrospect.
Hence, Ball’s experimental virtues are clearly distinguished from the
three other normative concepts. They comprehend a forth normative realm
of what scientists appreciate and value in their experimental practice
and which they call, in lack of a better term, ‘beautiful’. The book
provides no less than the first analysis of that realm regarding
chemistry.
Finally, Ball clearly distinguishes his
notion of
scientific beauty from artistic beauty – if beauty still plays a role
in the fine arts. In addition, he rejects the dull notion that a
molecule would be beautiful by way of its symmetry (pp. 195-6). While
his experimental virtues are scientific rather than artistic virtues,
he is confident that in the hands of an artist they could turn into the
skills to create true art.
I am sure many chemists will read the book
only to
learn about what the ten most beautiful experiments in chemistry are,
or how they could polish their public image by one or the other
association with art. I am also sure that readers, both chemists and
nonchemists, will greatly benefit from learning more about the history
of chemistry and about what matters in chemical experiments. However,
the intellectual strength of the book is that it provokes you to think
about how aesthetic values are related to experimental virtues, so that
it might end a period of silent rites.
Joachim Schummer:
Department of Philosophy, University of Darmstadt, Schloss, 64283
Darmstadt, Germany; js@hyle.org
Copyright © 2006 by HYLE and
Joachim Schummer
|