Symposium on the Philosophy
of Chemistry,
Universidad de los Andes, Bogota, Colombia, 21-23 July 2009
report by Andrés
Bernal, Guillermo Restrepo & José L. Villaveces*
Sponsored by the Universidad de los Andes,
this
symposium was organized by Professors José L. Villaveces from
the
Universidad de los Andes (Colombia) and Guillermo Restrepo from the
Universidad de Pamplona (Colombia). The meeting took place 21-23 July
2009 in Bogota (Colombia) at the campus of the Universidad de los Andes
with the participation, as international guests, of Eric Scerri and
Joachim Schummer, editors of the journals Foundations of Chemistry
and HYLE, respectively.
Although there are two international
scientific
journals devoted to philosophy of chemistry, the Latin American
presence in both is still incipient. Moreover, the International
Society for the Philosophy of Chemistry yearly organizes a symposium,
but this event is not always accessible to scholars from distant
corners of the globe, particularly because of the high cost of travel
and conference attendance. These were the reasons to organize this
first Symposium on the Philosophy of Chemistry in Latin America with
the first aim of bringing together worldwide leaders in the Philosophy
of Chemistry to discuss the most recent advances in the area and the
frontier themes to be studied in the future. The second aim of this
event was to spread Latin American results in philosophy of chemistry
and to facilitate the scientific discussion between all the
participants.
After the welcome words by Wolfram Baumann
(Head of
the Chemistry Department, Universidad de los Andes) and José L.
Villaveces (Vice-rector for Research, Universidad de los Andes), eight
papers were presented and two panel discussions took place. The
speakers came from Colombia, Germany, and USA; the conference language
was English.
Joachim Schummer (University of Karlsruhe,
Germany)
offered a broad perspective on the philosophy of chemistry, considering
four main points: the nature of chemistry and philosophical differences
regarding this question; the reducibility of chemistry to physics; the
epistemological limits of chemical knowledge; and the ethical relevance
of chemistry. He argued that differences in philosophy of chemistry
arise from ontological and epistemological priorities; that chemistry
demands concepts, theories and methods completely different from those
in physics; that there is an unavoidable element of incompleteness in
chemical knowledge; and that chemical synthesis creates special ethical
responsibilities for chemistry practitioners.
Eugenio J. Llanos (Scio Corporation,
Colombia)
considered the problem of defining the concepts of chemical reaction
and pure substance on solid grounds. He showed how the formalism of
axiomatic thermodynamics can be used as a frame for settling the matter
of defining these problematic concepts, both avoiding circularity in
the simultaneous definition of the two concepts and the use of
seemingly arbitrary, operative standards.
Eric Scerri (University of California at Los
Angeles, USA) spoke about recent developments on the concept of
chemical element. Starting from Paneth’s influential 1931 paper, he
elaborated on the debate developed over Paneth’s distinction between
two different aspects of the term ‘element’ – namely, an element as a
simple substance as opposed to an element as a basic substance. He then
argued that we actually need to consider three different senses of
element: basic substance, simple substance, and combined substance, the
first being an abstract entity underlying the other two. Finally, he
presented a structural realist position and developed the notion of the
periodic table as a structure.
Wilmer O. Leal (Universidad de Pamplona,
Colombia) elaborated on the idea that chemical properties are
relational, i.e.
that they arise from the interaction among chemicals. In so doing, he
showed results from the application of network theory and set-point
topology to the study of chemical elements, based upon the analysis of
binary compounds. Among the most important results, it was found that
traditional chemical groups such as alkali and alkaline earth metals as
well as halogens and noble gases are quite robust groups, i.e.
the elements belonging to each group are more similar to elements of
its group than to elements of other groups. Some metals and nonmetals
were found to be part of the topological boundary of semimetals.
Andrés Bernal (Universidad Nacional de
Colombia)
argued for the absence of corpuscularian elements at the core of
chemical theory, supporting his argument from a historical point of
view on several key passages of Lavoisier’s Traité
éleméntaire de chimie.
Along the way, he defended the idea that at the core of chemistry we
find an intrinsically relational theory of matter. Furthermore, he
proposed that the concept of relation as it appears in chemistry is
characterized by an emphasis on highly selective relations which, due
to epistemological concerns, leads to the adoption of internal relation
metaphysics.
Guillermo Restrepo (Universidad de Pamplona,
Colombia) showed that mathematical chemistry and philosophy of
chemistry, apparently two different fields, have similar fundamental
questions. Some of those questions are: What is chemistry? Which are
its foundations? How is chemistry related to e.g. physics,
biology, and mathematics? And how do other sciences influence
chemistry? He concluded that in spite of having common tasks,
mathematical chemists and philosophers of chemistry are not in touch
with each other, like the two sides of a coin. He ended his lecture
with the suggestion to change this mode of work and to try to interact
in a more efficient fashion by attending meetings and reading materials
from each other field in order to change the ‘coin’ into a ‘Möbius
strip’, a strip that only apparently has two sides but actually has
just one.
Edgar Vargas (Universidad de los Andes,
Colombia)
traced the origins of the natural philosophy of alchemy to principles
of the cultures of shamanism and craftsmanship. He pointed out that
dualistic and frequently sexual metaphors underlay the practice of
metallurgy, and linked these images to the substantialist theories of
the elements that appeared in ancient Greece and which were later
adopted by alchemy.
José L. Villaveces (Universidad de los
Andes,
Colombia) posed the question: What is a chemical structure? Taking as
an example the case of benzene, he showed that the currently accepted
hexagon for benzene came from symmetrical properties of substituted
benzenes. Thus, the ‘hexagon’ arose in an ontogenetic process from
symmetrical properties of a set of substances. Afterwards, he defined
chemical structure as a set of relations showing local symmetries.
Villaveces also pointed out the need to study the properties of the
substances and the carriers of these properties, i.e. chemical
formulae which become the words of a language. He ended his lecture by
drawing attention on the importance of studying such a language.
There were two panel discussions, the first
of
which dealt with the question: Why philosophy of chemistry? When
treating this topic, it turned out that fundamental chemical concepts
such as ‘pure substance’, ‘chemical element’, ‘chemical reaction’,
‘chemical properties’ and ‘chemical structure’ lack a formal
definition. Although different approaches to each of these concepts
were considered without final agreement, it was clear that it is
utterly important to understand them for a better understanding and
practice of chemistry. Another point discussed was the completeness of
chemical knowledge. In this respect it was argued that each new
substance increases the knowledge gap because many new reactivities
have to be tested. It was also mentioned the importance of using
mathematics in chemistry to shed light on the understanding of
chemistry itself, including classification techniques, network theory,
and graph theory among other branches of discrete mathematics. Finally,
stressing the relationship between chemistry and the ‘outer world’ (the
society), the importance of dealing with other philosophical questions
like those of ethics of chemistry was put forward. In general, the more
evident the importance of chemistry to the society is, the easier it is
to ponder on philosophical questions regarding chemistry.
The second panel discussion was on trends in
philosophy of chemistry. This discussion gathered several of the issues
raised by the previous lectures, which depict current trends in
philosophy of chemistry. One of the most discussed issues was the
relationship between the disciplines. The main suggestion was to move
from the Comtean hierarchical classification of sciences, where issues
like the reduction of one science to another are addressed, to
interdisciplinary sciences. Several contributions were about chemistry
education. There was agreement that chemistry is frequently taught as
if it were a part of physics. Because of that, philosophical aspects of
chemistry are left to philosophers of physics – an undesirable
situation that let students disregard the unique philosophical
characteristics of the chemical approach. Another point was the
importance of a mediator in interdisciplinary research who could be a
philosopher. Furthermore, there was agreement on the need to improve
the image of the philosophy of chemistry among both the chemical and
the philosophical communities, insofar as the first has a certain
‘philosophobia’ and the second a ‘chemophobia’. It was pointed out the
importance of a study on the image of the Philosophy of Chemistry among
the chemical community in order to address problems of its
popularization in this scientific group.
It was a pleasure to have young scientists
attending the meeting and even lecturing, which can be regarded as a
good sign for the continuity of these events and of the topics
discussed during the symposium. Attendances came from different fields,
namely from chemistry, philosophy, biology, and biophysics, a diversity
that was important and fruitful for the ensuing discussions. According
to the international guests (Schummer and Scerri) the meeting was not
just the invitation to the editors of the two journals devoted to the
philosophy of chemistry but a clear illustration of how Schummer’s and
Scerri’s ideas can be interlinked to yield new ideas and also to pose
new questions. It is the aim of the organizers to continue with this
kind of meetings in South America and they expect to have, in future
events, more participants from other South American countries.
Andrés Bernal:
Grupo de Química Teórica, Universidad Nacional de
Colombia, Bogotá, Colombia; afbernale@unal.edu.co
Guillermo Restrepo:
Laboratorio de Química Teórica, Universidad de Pamplona,
Pamplona,
Colombia; guillermorestrepo@gmail.com,
grestrepo@unipamplona.edu.co
José
L. Villaveces:
Grupo de Química Teórica, CEIBA, Universidad de los
Andes, Bogotá, Colombia; jlvillaveces@gmail.com,
jvillave@uniandes.edu.co
Copyright © 2010 by HYLE and
Guillermo Restrepo
|