‘Pathological Science’ is not Scientific Misconduct
(nor is it pathological)
Henry H. Bauer*
Abstract: ‘Pathological’ science implies scientific
misconduct: it should not happen and the scientists concerned ought to
know better. However, there are no clear and generally agreed definitions
of pathological science or of scientific misconduct. The canonical exemplars
of pathological science in chemistry (N-rays, polywater) as well as the
recent case of cold fusion in electrochemistry involved research practices
not clearly distinguishable from those in (revolutionary) science. The
concept of ‘pathological science’ was put forth nearly half a century ago
in a seminar and lacks justification in contemporary understanding of science
studies (history, philosophy, and sociology of science). It is time to
abandon the phrase.
Keywords: pathological science, scientific misconduct, cold
fusion, polywater, N-rays.
1. The Demarcation Issue
How to distinguish proper science from spurious imitations of it, in other
words pseudo-science, has long been discussed. Answers were suggested by
logical positivism, later via the hypothetico-deductive definition of science,
then using the purported falsifiability of scientific theories, and after
that Lakatos proposed the progressiveness or otherwise of research programs.
A satisfactory definition of science or formula for demarcation would
make it possible to classify specific investigations on the basis of criteria
applicable to real cases. Moreover, the classification should be achievable
contemporary with the actual investigation, it should not be necessary
to await the benefit of hindsight as to whether valid knowledge was obtained.
For example, a good demarcation scheme would have allowed contemporaries
of Mendel (rules of heredity) or of Wegener (occurrence of continental
drift) to testify that their ideas were worth attending to rather than
having them ignored for four decades before being taken up again.
This author agrees with Laudan (1983) that the search for such means
of demarcation will continue to be fruitless, for the following reasons.
Any definition of proper science should admit the practices long established
and held proper in such fields as chemistry, physics, biology, and geology
which, everyone agrees, are indeed sciences. But those practices are polyglot
in the extreme (Bauer 1992a; Committee on the Conduct of Science 1989).
Practicing scientists hardly ever set out deliberately to abide by some
criteria for being properly scientific; and it would therefore be surprising
in the extreme if they in fact somehow did all so abide.
Modern science depends on communication among and review by peers. One
might therefore suggest that isolation from a given research community
would be grounds for classing an investigation as pseudo-science. But isolation
is a matter of degree, and some iconoclastic individuals have produced
valid scientific breakthroughs while working largely alone – Einstein,
for instance, or the previously mentioned Mendel and Wegener.
A less sociological view is that of Kuhn (1970) who contrasts the occasional
‘scientific revolutions’ with normal science in which puzzles are solved
without calling into question long-standing data, methods, or theories.
Accepting those three things as the essential aspects of science leads
to another possible scheme for demarcation (Bauer 2001a, pp. 9-11). In
normal science, no great novelty in any of the three is involved. Scientific
revolutions introduce startling novelty in just one of the three;
typically in theory as with relativity or quantum mechanics, but it might
also be in data as with the recognition of radioactivity, or in method
as with radio-astronomy. Substantial novelty simultaneously in two of the
three facets characterizes such ventures as those of Mendel and Wegener,
which Stent (1972) described as "premature" science. Finally, attempting
novelty in all three aspects of science signifies wholesale cutting loose
from established knowledge and might therefore be classed as practicing
pseudo-science – were it not for the fact that valid knowledge might sometimes
result from such jumps into the deep unknown; natural history, after all,
was largely ab initio yet nevertheless led to modern science. The
study of such purported phenomena as dowsing or psychic effects may yet
yield useful knowledge despite the lack of established data, methods, or
theories about them.
Even though widely accepted demarcation criteria are lacking (or, for
that matter, general agreement about what defines science), observers and
critics of science as well as scientists themselves do freely apply the
term ‘pseudo-science’ to such things as UFOlogy and parapsychology. But
a detailed comparison of how investigations are carried out in such areas
and in the natural and social sciences fails to turn up clear-cut distinctions
(Bauer 2001a). That failure is well-nigh pre-ordained, since certain subjects
often labeled ‘pseudo’ subsequently become, if not accepted science then
at least no longer pseudo: mainstream researchers now study acupuncture,
generally despised as pseudo in Western science until the 1970s; ball lightning,
long dismissed as non-existent, is now studied by physicists and meteorologists.
And so on (Bauer 2001a, pp. 23-24).
2. What is ‘pathological science’?
While philosophers have generally employed the term ‘pseudo-science’, many
people interested in what is bad science have applied other terms to various
controversial topics: Fads and Fallacies of Science by the science
pundit Martin Gardner (1957) is a classic. Richard Feynman (1974) talked
about "cargo-cult" science. Another physicist has recently titled his book
Voodoo
Science (Park 2000). But the only other term than ‘pseudo-science’
that has achieved wide use is ‘pathological science’; and it has been applied
most often to cases best known to chemists and physicists (N-rays, polywater,
cold fusion), perhaps because the term was originated by the great physical
chemist Irving Langmuir (1932 Nobel Prize).
Langmuir’s canonical text on ‘pathological science’ is not, however,
a technical or philosophical treatise but simply a talk given in 1953 and
published in 1968. Langmuir described pathological science as "the science
of things that aren’t so", using as examples the Davis-Barnes Effect, N-rays,
mitogenetic rays, the Allison Effect, extrasensory perception, and flying
saucers (Langmuir 1968).
Langmuir offered six characteristics of pathological science:
-
The magnitude of the effect is substantially independent of the intensity
of the causative agent.
-
The effect is of a magnitude that remains close to the limits of detectability;
or, many measurements are necessary because of the very low statistical
significance of the results.
-
It makes claims of great accuracy.
-
It puts forth fantastic theories contrary to experience.
-
Criticisms are met by ad hoc excuses.
-
The ratio of supporters to critics rises up to somewhere near 50 percent
and then falls gradually to oblivion.
However – in keeping with the genesis of these ideas in an informal seminar
for researchers at the General Electric Laboratories – Langmuir made no
attempt to justify these characteristics as invariably present, or some
of them as being sufficient to diagnose pathology. In either case, they
do not provide useful criteria for distinguishing bad science from good
science (Bauer 1984, pp. 145-46; Physics Today, 1990a, b); many
praised pieces of research satisfy one or more of Langmuir’s criteria for
pathology. Richard Rhodes (1997) has pointed out, for example, that Langmuir’s
measures of pathological science fit nicely the discovery of prions for
which Prusiner received a Nobel Prize. High-energy physics deals increasingly
with phenomena that can only be detected by computer manipulation in order
to remove background noise, in other words the effects are – Langmuir’s
second criterion – "of a magnitude that remains close to the limits of
detectability" and "many measurements are necessary". The use of atomic
frequencies as standards of time "makes claims of great accuracy" indeed,
to 10 decimal places and more. Criterion 4, "fantastic theories contrary
to experience", describes well much of modern cosmology – Big Bang, black
holes, strings, 11-dimensional universes and many-world theories, Anthropic
Principles, and so on. Criterion 5 describes as pathological what Lakatos
(1976) pointed out to be characteristic of regular science, the ad hoc
modification of subsidiary parts of a theory in order to maintain the core
beliefs. Nor does criterion 6 apply to what not only Langmuir but many
other people continue to regard as genuinely pathological, such things
as parapsychology, UFOs, water dowsing: the ratio of supporters shows no
signs of dwindling over a period of decades. (That last point reveals a
lacuna in quantitative data about science: we do not know what may be ‘normal’
growth in research. Langmuir’s notion, repeated by Bennion & Neuton
(1976) and Franks (1981, p. 128), that pathological science is like
an epidemic, with a rapid rise and then a rapid decline in publications,
is a speculation, it is not empirically based. I would speculate by contrast
that many non-pathological fields that become ‘hot’ show a rapid rise followed
by a marked decline, high-temperature superconductors for example. Actual
data on this score being lacking, no diagnosis of pathology should be based
on it.)
Langmuir’s criteria, then, are no more valid than the many other suggestions
as to how to distinguish good science from pseudo-science (Bauer 1984,
chapter 8; Laudan 1983). Certainly, appeals to the classic ‘scientific
method’ are not workable (Bauer 1992a, pp. 57-61). Nevertheless, it remains
common for scientists to rely on Langmuir’s notions rather than on modern
views in science studies and for naive discussions of ‘pathological science’
to appear even in periodicals that might be expected to draw on referees
versed in history or philosophy or sociology of science; for example, in
1992 American Scientist had an article castigating as pathological
"infinite dilution" studies of the effectiveness of certain biological
agents, polywater, and cold fusion (Rousseau 1992).
That Langmuir’s ideas have seemed convincing to scientists is illustrated
by the publication of his talk 15 years after it was given and by re-publication
a couple of decades later (Langmuir 1985, 1989). The 1985 version added
such examples of pathological science as water dowsing, the canals of Mars,
certain reported photomechanical and electromechanical effects, radar observations
of Venus, polywater, biological effects of magnetic fields, and the detection
of gravity waves. One or another of these versions of Langmuir’s talk continues
to be cited as authoritative: several references per year are listed in
the Science Citation Index through the 1990s; and there are some
uncountably larger number in such periodicals as Skeptical Inquirer
that specialize in discussions of pseudo-science and pathological science
but are not scanned for the Science Citation Index.
3. Scientific Misconduct
Scientific misconduct is no better defined a concept than is pathological
science. An increasing rate of uncovered cases of fraud over the last two
decades, chiefly the faking of evidence in clinical medicine (Broad &
Wade 1982) led to much discussion of possible ways to prevent and to sanction
misconduct by scientists. Journals devoted specifically to issues of ethical
research were founded, for example Accountability in Research in
1993 (a quarterly, ISSN 0898-9621) and Science and Engineering Ethics
in 1995 (also a quarterly, ISSN 1471-5546).
It has proved impossible to arrive at a definition of scientific misconduct
that could be approved by US government agencies (National Institutes of
Health, National Science Foundation) as well as by professional scientific
societies and industries engaged in scientific research. A Web-site originally
sponsored by the National Science Foundation (The Online Ethics Center
for Science and Engineering, http://onlineethics.org/)
lists many codes of ethical conduct established by various professional
groups in engineering, mathematics, and science; the Center for Study of
Ethics in the Professions at the Illinois Institute of Technology makes
available a similarly wide range of such codes (http://csep.iit.edu/codes/science.html).
The failure to achieve a science-wide consensus underscores how the
approved practices in science vary from specialty to specialty. Perhaps
the closest to an ‘official’ statement about scientific misconduct is the
"Model Policy for Responding to Allegations of Scientific Misconduct" developed
by the Office of Research Integrity of the Department of Health and Human
Services (the Office was originally within the National Institutes of Health):
O. Scientific misconduct or misconduct in science means
fabrication, falsification, plagiarism, or other practices that seriously
deviate from those that are commonly accepted within the scientific community
for proposing, conducting, or reporting research. It does not include honest
error or honest differences in interpretations or judgments of data. [http://ori.dhhs.gov/html/misconduct/model.asp]
To apply this model, one needs to know what the "commonly accepted" practices
in science are. In the following analysis of notorious cases often called
‘pathological science’, it will be shown that the perpetrators followed
in their criticized work the same practices as they had in their generally
approved research.
4. The exemplars of pathological science
Certain researches have been so disdained as to warrant, in the eyes of
many scientists and observers, the epithet ‘pathological’ or ‘pseudo-science’.
That clearly implies that the criticized work is in some fashion different
from good, proper scientific work. But in what manner?
Rousseau (1992) decries the difference as the "loss of objectivity".
But it is very naive indeed to suggest that unless scientists practice
objectivity they are being pathological. Objectivity in science is owing
not to its practice by individuals but to the mutual critiquing that decreases
subjectivity (Bauer 1992a).
The most frequently cited instances of pathological science are in physical
chemistry: N-rays from the beginning of the 20th
century, cold fusion from the last decade of that century, and polywater
in between (late 1960s). Yet in each of those cases, detailed examination
of what the central researchers actually did reveals that they were doing
nothing different in the supposedly ‘pathological’ work than in their other,
considerably lauded scientific research.
N-Rays
N-rays have been referred to innumerable times, but the best scholarly
discussions are by Derek de Solla Price (1975) and Mary Joe Nye (1980).
René Blondlot, in France, at the University of Nancy (hence N-rays),
announced his discovery of N-rays in 1903: a new form of radiation, emitted
by both living and inanimate bodies, able to penetrate aluminum but not
lead, able to be refracted by aluminum prisms as light is refracted by
glass. For several years, N-rays were studied by scores of scientists in
France and hundreds of papers were published. Yet scientists in other countries
were not able to reproduce the radiation. An American physicist, Robert
Wood, observed the experiments in Blondlot’s lab: in darkness, visual observation
was used to detect on measuring scales the spots of light that N-rays produced.
Surreptitiously in the darkened room, Wood removed the aluminum prism.
The measurements continued to be read out as before. Evidently optical
illusion was causing spots of light to be imagined at expected values along
the scales. This demonstration convinced almost all the scientific community
that N-rays do not exist; but Blondlot and a few others persisted in their
belief that N-rays were real.
So presumably what was pathological here was a reliance on visual observation
under conditions – a darkened room – where optical illusions readily occur.
(One modern test for glaucoma is to note over what field of view one can
detect flashes of light on a dark background. Anyone who has taken such
a test knows that one ‘sees’ some number of flashes that are not actually
there.) But Blondlot was a distinguished member of the French scientific
establishment. He had been particularly praised for showing that X-rays
moved at the speed of light which he had established by the same method
of visual observation, in that case variations in the apparent intensity
of electric sparks. Blondlot was therefore very unfortunate; but how can
he be blamed for continuing to use a technique that had been so successful?
"The curious error of N-rays is much more a sort of mass hallucination,
proceeding from an entirely reasonable beginning" (Price 1975, p. 159).
Moreover, the facts Blondlot reported were confirmed by a number
of his fellow scientists, not only in his laboratory but also elsewhere
in France; which gave Blondlot good reason to think his discovery a genuine
one. And early in the 20th century, Blondlot
was far from alone in looking for new types of radiation. X-rays and radioactivity
had been discovered just a decade earlier, and some years before that Hertz
had discovered radio waves.
If pathological science is to be regarded as scientific misconduct,
then there would need to be some indication that there had been willful
deception, or at least quite egregious incompetence. The record
does not support indictment of Blondlot on either of those scores. In point
of fact, if anyone behaved unethically during this episode, it would seem
to be Robert Wood, who deliberately and surreptitiously interfered with
the experiments in order to deceive the experimenters; yet I know of no
discussion of the case that does anything but praise Wood for his demonstration
that N-rays are not real phenomena.
Polywater
The most thorough discussion of the polywater affair is due to Felix Franks
(1981), who was himself engaged in research on chemical and physical aspects
of water for many years. He was not himself involved in any work on polywater,
but was acquainted with many of the people who were.
Surface science at mid-20th-century
was studied perhaps more intensively in the Soviet Union than elsewhere,
including how the properties of water are affected by surfaces. In the
early 1960s, Nikolai Fedyakin observed that a column of water sealed in
a narrow tube slowly and spontaneously formed a second column that did
not freeze or boil like ordinary water. A few years later, the internationally
respected Boris Derjaguin brought this phenomenon to wide attention as
‘anomalous water’, which had a 40% higher density than ordinary water and
different refractive index and vapor pressure as well as freezing and boiling
points.
As with N-rays, the people who studied polywater used the same techniques
and general approach as in their other work. Unlike with N-rays, scientists
all over the world reported the preparation and investigation of polywater;
indeed the very name is owing to a prominent American spectroscopist, Ellis
Lippincott. The renowned British physicist J.D. Bernal called anomalous
water "the most important physical-chemical discovery of this century"
(Franks 1981, p. 49). Polywater was discussed at several of the prestigious
annual Gordon Research Conferences (Franks 1981, p. 124).
So what was wrong about polywater?
It turned out that polywater is actually contaminated water. But before
one jumps to the conclusion that those who studied polywater were sloppy
in their laboratory technique, one ought to realize that the level of impurities
responsible for the effect was lower than could be detected by then-available
methods. Moreover, the precise nature and source of the contaminants remained
unclear: "several of the questions […] raised have not yet received satisfactory
answers [… namely] that water vapor reacts with quartz more readily
than does liquid water […]. Is water adsorbed from the vapor phase onto
silicate surfaces a much better solvent than bulk water? Is it more acidic
than bulk water?" (Franks 1981, pp. 145-46). The Russian workers had used
quartz rather than glass tubing precisely because glass was known to release
impurities into water whereas quartz had not been known to. The first major
American publication on polywater had made a point of the lack of spectroscopic
evidence of any contamination (Franks 1981, p. 71).
So the polywater researchers can hardly be accused of poor, let alone
pathological laboratory practice. But it has also been suggested that polywater
should have been dismissed on theoretical grounds: the raised boiling point
showed that polywater was more stable than ordinary water, and therefore
thermodynamics would decree that all ordinary water would have spontaneously
turned into polywater, releasing energy in the process. Nobel laureate
Richard Feynman remarked by hindsight (Eisenberg 1981) that there could
be no such thing as polywater because if there were, there would also be
an animal that need not eat food: it would just drink water and excrete
polywater, using the energy difference to maintain its metabolism. Such
thermodynamic reasoning is invalid, however. It is not enough that one
substance be more stable than another for it to transform readily into
the other: there must be some feasible mechanism by which it can do so.
Nature affords innumerable examples of substances of different stability
coexisting. For instance, diamond is a more stable form of pure carbon
than is graphite. By Feynman’s reasoning, there should be organisms that
get their energy by imbibing carbon in the form of graphite (from the ashes
of forest fires, say) and excreting diamonds.
Again as with N-rays, the scientists who were tricked by Nature have
been accused of unethical behavior, for example rushing too quickly to
publish; yet those who discovered that contamination was the problem were
equally guilty of rushing to publication – though they were not criticized
for it (Franks 1981, p. 159).
Cold Fusion
The most recent major outcry over ‘pathological science’ was occasioned
by ‘cold fusion’. A number of books about this episode have appeared, all
of them quite strongly pro- or con-. This author, who himself worked in
electrochemistry from the early 1950s to the late 1970s, has discussed
the merits and defects of these books in several reviews (Bauer 1991; 1992b,
c; 1995).
In 1989, Martin Fleischmann and Stanley Pons announced at a press conference
at the University of Utah that they had brought about nuclear fusion at
room temperature in an electrochemical cell: they had measured heat production
too great to explain by other than nuclear processes.
Many physicists dismissed the claims as impossible from the outset,
yet confirmations were being announced from all over the world. Within
months, however, many of these were withdrawn; other laboratories reported
failures to replicate the effect; and a committee empaneled by the US Department
of Energy concluded that there was nothing worth pursuing in these claims.
Within a year or two, those working on cold fusion had become separated
from mainstream scientific communities, holding separate conferences and
often publishing in other than mainstream publications. However, at the
present time, a dozen years after the initial announcement, a considerable
number of properly qualified people continue to believe the chief claim,
that nuclear reactions can be achieved at ambient temperatures under electrochemical
conditions (Beaudette 2000).
What have Fleischmann and Pons been accused of that was ‘pathological’?
They had announced their discovery at a news conference and not in peer-reviewed
publication. They had failed to reveal all details of their procedures.
The heat effect remained elusive: no one could set up the experiment and
guarantee that excess heat would be observed, sometimes it was and sometimes
not. They had performed incompetent measurements of nuclear products and
then fudged the results. They had failed to understand that nuclear reactions
would inevitably release radiation, and that the level of radiation corresponding
to the heat claimed to have been generated would have been lethal. Nuclear
theory in any case showed that fusion could not occur under such mild conditions,
it required higher temperatures and pressures to many orders of magnitudes,
as in the interior of stars.
But of all those criticisms, only the one about fudging nuclear measurements
can be sustained, and that does not bear on the issue of whether or not
cold fusion is a real phenomenon.
Announcing results first at news conferences has become standard practice
in hot fields, for example molecular biology and genetic engineering. It
was routine during the initial years of excitement about high-temperature
superconductors. Also in that field, some workers quite deliberately put
misleading information into their publications, correcting them at the
last moment only, in order to preserve secrecy (Felt & Nowotny 1992;
Roy 1989).
Lack of replicability does not mean that a phenomenon is necessarily
spurious. Semiconductors did not become transistors and microchips in the
1930s because the presence of then-unsuspected, then-undetectably-small
amounts of impurities made the phenomena irreproducible, elusive. Certain
effects of electromagnetic fields on living systems remained difficult
to reproduce for a century or more (Bauer 2001a, pp. 125, 132-33). Perhaps
only electrochemists would recognize how vast is the number of experimental
variables that might affect reproducibility in cold-fusion systems: almost
innumerable variations in the physical characteristics of the electrodes
and in the electrical regimen as well as all sorts of possible contaminants,
conceivably active at levels that might be virtually impossible to detect
by other means than their interference with the looked-for effect.
As to theoretical possibility, "Although cold fusion was, in terms of
‘ordinary’ physics, absurd, it was not obviously so; it contravened no
fundamental laws of nature" (Lindley 1990, p. 376). Physics Nobelist Julian
Schwinger was among those who proposed explanations for how cold fusion
might occur. It may be well to recall in this connection that lasers and
masers were also regarded as impossible before their discovery, and indeed
by some eminent people even after they had been demonstrated (Townes
1999).
Once again, as with N-rays and polywater, it turns out that nothing
occurred that could rightly be called pathological. The leading cold-fusion
researchers went at their work just as they had at the other research that
had established their good reputation, in Fleischmann’s case sufficiently
distinguished as to warrant a Fellowship of the Royal Society. Fleischmann
had always been known as an adventurous thinker, the sort of person – like
the astrophysicist Thomas Gold (1999) – whose suggestions are always worth
attending to even when they do not work out. His competence was beyond
question, and it was not at all uncharacteristic for him to follow apparently
far-out hunches. Sometimes they had paid off for him. Moreover, he had
ample grounds from earlier work to look for unusual phenomena when electrolyzing
heavy water at palladium electrodes, and he had quite rational grounds
for speculating that nuclear reactions might proceed in the solid state
under quite different conditions than in plasmas (Beaudette 2000, chap.
3).
The single criticism that is not to be gainsaid concerns how Fleischmann
and Pons altered the reported results from initial attempts to measure
radiation from their cells. But there is more to be noted here about such
apparent instances of scientific misconduct. Fleischmann and Pons were
tempted into these actions because they had tried to make measurements
without properly learning all the ins and outs of the technique: they thought
they could measure radiation by just taking a radiation meter and placing
it near their cell. In point of fact, a great deal needs to be known about
circumstances that can affect the functioning of such instruments (temperature,
for example) and about how to eliminate background signals, as well as
about how to interpret the measurements. In this, Fleischmann and Pons
were falling into the same trap as many of their critics who, without experience
of electrochemistry, thought they could connect together some cells and
batteries and palladium electrodes and test within days or weeks what the
experienced electrochemists had struggled for several years to bring about.
The transfer of expertise across disciplinary boundaries affords great
challenges, and this instance illustrates that a superficial view might
label as misconduct what is basically a natural result of failing to recognize
how intricately specialized are the approaches of every sort of research.
Much of the fuss about cold fusion is understandable as an argument between
electrochemists and physicists as to whether empirical data from electrochemical
experiments is to be more believed or less believed than apparently opposing
nuclear theory (Beaudette 2000). To electrochemists it may seem perverse,
possibly even scientific misconduct, to rule out of the realm of possibility
competently obtained results because some theory in physics pronounces
them impossible. To nuclear physicists, it may seem incompetence verging
on scientific misconduct for electrochemists to invoke nuclear explanations
just because they cannot understand where the heat in their experiments
comes from.
As in the case of N-rays, one can plausibly level charges of scientific
misconduct against those who denounced the cold-fusion studies. A journalist
baselessly charged a graduate student with falsifying evidence of the production
of tritium and this charge was published in Nature. The legitimacy
of work by a distinguished Professor at Texas A & M University was
questioned in two separate, long-drawn-out investigations that ultimately
found him innocent of any wrongdoing. One participant in the cold-fusion
controversy suggested that critics were guilty of "pathological skepticism"
(Accountability in Research 2000).
5. Paradigm-threatening research
There is no fussing over instances of ‘pathological science’ within the
realms of what Kuhn has termed ‘normal’ science, the sort of research that
most scientists are engaged in, that adds detail to the existing stock
of knowledge without bringing into question accepted modes of explanation.
‘Pathological’ science is rather revolutionary science that has
(according to the mainstream view) gone so egregiously wrong as to warrant
passionate
denunciation.
But the mainstream is always antagonistic to highly novel discoveries
or suggestions, even when they become acceptable later: any suggestion
that paradigms need to be changed is routinely resisted (Barber
1961), sometimes by effectively ignoring the claims (Stent 1972). Yet until
a revolutionary suggestion has been adequately investigated, it cannot
be known whether it will in the future become a lauded instance of scientific
progress or whether it will be relegated to the dustbin of ‘pathological
science’. Those who took the risk to follow the new possibility are later
praised or denounced according to how lucky or unlucky they were: to become
fascinated with an unknown that turned out to be a good lead, or with an
unknown that turned out to be a dead end.
In point of fact, a notable number of highly accomplished, creative
scientists have suffered varying degrees of calumny from mainstream critics
– quite often, critics whose accomplishments do not compare with those
of the people they criticize – after some of their most ambitious work
failed to find approval or agreement from the mainstream. A short list
of such cases includes (Bauer 1996 and 2001b, chap., "Luck – or the lack
of it"; Bauer and Huyghe 2000):
-
Dual Nobelist Linus Pauling, according to some the greatest chemist of
the 20th century, was unconscionably denigrated
by some critics for his later work on the value of large doses of vitamin
C and other vitamins.
-
C.G. Barkla came to grief over the claimed J-phenomenon (Wynne 1976, Wallis
1985) shown by X-rays; yet his Nobel Prize in physics, in 1917, had been
awarded for work on X-rays.
-
Sir Arthur Eddington, early exponent of relativity and pioneer in theoretical
astronomy, produced a ‘fundamental theory’ that is generally regarded as
numerological nonsense (Slater 1957).
-
Astronomer Halton Arp was refused further use of telescopes in the United
States for denying contemporary dogma concerning red-shifts (Arp 1987,
Marshall 1990).
-
Hannes Alfvén was awarded the Nobel Prize in 1970 for work on space
plasma, yet "many regard his cosmological ideas as belonging to the fringe,
and researchers who study his cosmology say they get no public support"
(Brush 1990, Marshall 1990).
Just as with Blondlot, Derjaguin, and Fleischmann, there is nothing in
the record to suggest that these accomplished scientists had taken a different
approach in that part of their work that was called egregiously wrong as
they had taken in that part of their work for which they had received high
praise. One cannot therefore accuse them of scientific misconduct. It is
just the case that seeking new knowledge is fraught with difficulties;
and there is no formula for scientific research procedures that can guarantee
that false trails will not be followed.
Still, some critics have argued, Blondlot and these other practitioners
of ‘pathological’ science ought to have recognized their errors after their
more level-headed mainstream colleagues had pointed them out. Here again,
however, one needs to distinguish normal science from (potentially) revolutionary
science. The great breakthroughs that are praised by hindsight also came
about because their proponents stubbornly, pig-headedly continued to go
their own way despite lack of agreement from their peers. As Nobelist Martin
Perl put it, "you have to be stubborn and willing to be alone" (Mooney
1996). Even when one’s hunch seems not to be borne out by initial experiments,
or if success is fleeting or irreproducible, being stubborn can pay off:
for example, Jacob and Brenner on the way to discovering messenger RNA,
"sure of the correctness of our hypothesis [… we] started our experiment
over and over again" (Grinnell 1996).
The most striking potential discoveries bring about revolutionary paradigm
shifts. The accepted rules and procedures for doing normal science are
not adequate to bring about potentially revolutionary science: as is well
known, hard cases make bad laws. Apparently unreasonable persistence and
willingness to follow far-out hunches are needed for the great breakthroughs,
but they may equally lead to intellectual disasters. Similarly headstrong
researchers of similar background, for example Albert Szent-Györgyi
and Wilhelm Reich, acquired in the one case a Nobel Prize and in the other
the label of crank (Bauer 1992a, p. 61), yet it is far from obvious where
and when Reich took a turn that would irretrievably lead him into error
(Bauer 2001a, pp. 156-63). As I.J. Good (1998) has remarked, geniuses are
cranks who happen to be right; as equally, of course, some cranks may be
geniuses who happen to be wrong.
The manner in which research is carried on depends inevitably on the
state of the art in the particular specialty. There is inevitably more
speculation and persistent sticking with hunches in areas where comparatively
little is known than in well traversed fields (Bauer 2001a). The most innovative
and exploratory investigations inevitably carry higher risks of going wrong.
They will more frequently lead down false trails than to genuine paradigm
shifts; but when they succeed, the success is also more significant than
are the routine, everyday successes of normal science.
Nothing is to be gained by castigating those who followed false paths
in good faith and with the honest determination to add to human knowledge.
‘Pathological science’ is an epithet applied to potentially revolutionary
discoveries that did not pan out. The passionate disdain implied by the
phrase is not justified by the actions of those who have been so criticized.
Rather, it may be an instance of odium scholasticum: the criticism
is so furious not because the thing is so far removed from the acceptable,
but because it comes so infuriatingly close to being remarkably right.
References
Accountability in Research: Policies and Quality Assurance, 8
(2000), nos. 1 & 2, pp. 1-188 (a special double issue concentrating
on the cold-fusion controversy).
Arp, H.: 1987, Quasars, Redshifts and Controversies, Interstellar
Media, Berkeley (CA).
Barber, B.: 1961, ‘Resistance by scientists to scientific discovery’,
Science,134,
596-602.
Bauer, H.H.: 1984, Beyond Velikovsky: The History of a Public Controversy,
University of Illinois Press, Urbana & Chicago (IL).
Bauer, H.H.: 1991, ‘Review of Frank Close, Too Hot to Handle: The Race
for Cold Fusion’, Journal of Scientific Exploration, 5, 267-70.
Bauer, H.H.: 1992a, Scientific Literacy and the Myth of the Scientific
Method, University of Illinois Press, Urbana & Chicago (IL).
Bauer, H.H.: 1992b, ‘Review of E. F. Mallove, Fire from Ice: Searching
for the Truth Behind the Cold Fusion Furor’, Journal of Scientific Exploration,
6,
81-4.
Bauer, H.H.: 1992c, ‘Review of J. R. Huizenga, Cold Fusion: The Scientific
Fiasco of the Century’, Journal of Scientific Exploration, 6,
395-400.
Bauer, H.H.: 1995, ‘Review of G. Taubes, Bad Science: The Short Life
and Weird Times of Cold Fusion’, Journal of Scientific Exploration,
9,
301-307.
Bauer, H.H.: 1996, ‘The fault lies in their stars, and not in them –
when distinguished scientists lapse into pseudo-science’, Seminar, 8 February,
Center for the Study of Science in Society, Virginia Polytechnic Institute
& State University; ‘The myth of the scientific method’, Keynote Address,
26 June, 3rd Annual Josephine L. Hopkins Foundation Workshop for Science
Journalists, Cornell University.
Bauer, H.H.: 2001a, Science or Pseudoscience: Magnetic Healing, Psychic
Phenomena, and Other Heterodoxies, University of Illinois Press, Urbana
& Chicago (IL).
Bauer, H.H.: 2001b, Fatal Attractions: The Troubles with Science,
Paraview Press, New York (in press).
Bauer, H.H.; Huyghe, P.: 2000, ‘Those who lapsed’, http://www.mightywords.com
(in the "Science" category).
Beaudette, C.G.: 2000, Excess Heat: Why Cold Fusion Research Prevailed,
Oak Grove Press, Bristol (ME).
Bennion, B.C.; Neuton, L. A.: 1976, ‘The epidemiology of research on
"anomalous water"’, Journal of the American Society for Information
Science, January-February, 53-56.
Broad, W.; Wade, N.: 1982, Betrayers of the Truth: Fraud and Deceit
in the Halls of Science, Simon & Schuster, New York.
Brush, S.G.: 1990, ‘Prediction and theory development: Alfvén
on space plasma phenomena’, Eos, 71 (no. 2, 9 January), 19-33.
Committee on the Conduct of Science: 1989, On Being a Scientist,
National Academy Press, Washington.
Eisenberg, D.: 1981, ‘A scientific gold rush’, Science,213,
1104-5 (review of Franks 1981).
Felt, U.; Nowotny, H.: 1992, ‘Striking gold in the 1990s: the discovery
of high-temperature superconductivity and its impact on the science system’,
Science,
Technology & Human Values, 17, 506-31.
Feynman, R.P.: 1974, ‘Cargo-cult science’, Engineering and Science,
June, 10-13.
Franks, F.: 1981, Polywater, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).
Gardner, M.: 1957, Fads & Fallacies In the Name of Science,
Dover, New York (1st ed., In the Name
of Science, G.P. Putnam’s Sons, 1952).
Gold, T.: 1999, The Deep Hot Biosphere, Copernicus (Springer),
New York.
Good, I.J.: 1998, ‘The self-consistency of the kinematics of special
relativity, IV.’ Physics Essays, 11 (no. 2), 248-63.
Grinnell, F.: 1996, ‘Ambiguity in the practice of science’, Science,272,
333.
Kuhn, T.S.: 1970, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press (2nd ed., enlarged;
1st ed. 1962).
Lakatos, I.: 1976, ‘History of science and its rational reconstruction’,
in: C. Howson (ed.), Method and Appraisal in the Physical Sciences,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (UK), pp. 1-40.
Langmuir, I.: 1968, ‘Pathological science’, Report no. 68-C-035, April,
General Electric R&D Center; transcribed by R. N. Hall (contains transcript
of question-and-answer session).
Langmuir, I.: 1985, ‘Pathological science: scientific studies based
on non-existent phenomena’, Speculations in Science and Technology,
8
(no. 2), 77-94 (new edition of Langmuir 1968 with a different Epilogue
and added references but without question-and-answer section).
Langmuir, I.: 1989, ‘Pathological Science’, Physics Today, October,
36-48 (shorter revised Epilogue with fewer references than in Langmuir
1985, and no question-and-answer section).
Laudan, L.: 1983, ‘The demise of the demarcation problem’, in: R.S.
Cohen & L. Laudan (eds.), Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis,
D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 111-127.
Lindley, D.: 1990, ‘The embarrassment of cold fusion’, Nature,
344,
375-76.
Marshall, E.: 1990, ‘Science beyond the pale’, Science, 249,
14-16.
Mooney, C.J.: 1996, ‘Notes from academe: Sweden’, Chronicle of Higher
Education, 5 January, p. A63.
Nye, M.J.: 1980, ‘N rays: an episode in the history and psychology of
science’, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 11
(pt. 1), 125-56.
Park, R.L.: 2000, Voodoo Science: The Road from Foolishness to Fraud,
Oxford University Press, New York.
Physics Today: 1990a, ‘Second opinions on "pathological science"’,
March, pp. 13, 15, 108, 110, 112 (letters from Christopher Cooper, Peter
A. Sturrock, K. Ramakrishna Rao, Peter R. Phillips, Dean Radin, Robert
G. Fleagle, Albert A. Bartlett, and Michael Wixom).
Physics Today: 1990b, ‘"Pathological science": erroneous epilogue?’,
April, pp. 13, 15, 108, 110, 112 (letters from Walter L. Faust & David
J. Michel, John J. Gilman & Jack H. Westbrook, James M. Galligan, Yasuo
Nannichi, Kyle Forinash & William D. Rumsey; with reply by Robert N.
Hall).
Price, D. de S.: 1975, Science Since Babylon, Yale University
Press, New Haven (enlarged ed., originally 1961).
Rhodes, R.: 1997, ‘Pathological science’, New Yorker, 1 December,
54-59.
Rousseau, D.L.: 1992, ‘Cases studies in pathological science’, American
Scientist, 80 (January-February), 54-63.
Roy, R.: 1989, ‘Views on nuclear fusion’, Chemical & Engineering
News, 15 May, p. 2.
Slater, N.B.: 1957, The Development and Meaning of Eddington’s ‘Fundamental
Theory’, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (UK).
Stent, G.: 1972, ‘Prematurity and uniqueness in scientific discovery’,
Scientific
American, December, pp. 84-93.
Townes, C.H.: 1999, How the Laser Happened, Oxford University
Press, New York & Oxford, pp. 65, 69.
Wallis, R.: 1985, ‘Science and pseudo-science’, Social Science Information,
24,
585-601.
Wynne, B.: 1976, ‘C.G. Barkla and the J phenomenon: a case study in
the treatment of deviance in physics’, Social Studies of Science,
6,
307-47.
Henry H. Bauer:
1306 Highland Circle, Blacksburg, VA 24060-5623, U.S.A.; hhbauer@vt.edu
Copyright Ó
2002 by HYLE and Henry H. Bauer
|